The Making of Mind
A Personal Account of
Soviet Psychology
A. R. Luria
Michael Cole and Sheila Cole, eds.
Introduction and Epilogue
by Micbael Cole
HARVARD UNIVERSITY PRESS
Cambridge, Massachusetts,
and London. England
copyright @ 1979 by the President
and Fellows of Harvard College
All rights reserved
Printed in the United States of
America
Editorial work on the autobiography was supported in
part by a grant from the Alfred P. Sloan Foundation.
10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2
Library
of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data
Luria, Aleksandr Romanovich,
1902The making of mind.
Bibliography: p.
Includes index.
1. Luria, Aleksandr
Romanovich, 1902
2. Psychologists‑Russia‑Biography.
3. Psychology
Russia. I. Cole, Michael, 1938‑
11. Cole, Sheila.
III. Title. [DNI‑M: 1. Psychology‑Personal
narrative.
WZ100 L9671
15F109.L87A35 15Y.092'4 79‑15203
ISBN 0‑674‑54326‑2
(cloth)
ISBN 0‑674‑54327‑0
(paper)
Contents
Introduction: The Historical Context 1
1. Apprenticeship 17
2.Moscow 28
3. Vygotsky 38
4.Cultural Differences in Thinking 58
5. Mental Development in Twins 81
6. Verbal Regulation of Behavior 104
7. Disturbance of Brain Functions 120
8. Neuropsychology in World War 11 138
9. Mechanisms of the Brain 157
10.Romantic Science 174
Epilogue: A Portrait of Luria 189
Bibliography 229
Index 232
Introduction:
The Historical Context
JUST AFTER the turn of this century the
German psycholgist Flermann Ebbinghaus reflected that psychology "has a
long past,' but a short history." Ebbinghaus was commenting on the fact
that whereas psychological theorizing has existed as long as recorded thought,
only a quarter of a century had passed since the founding of the first
scientific groups that were self‑consciously known as "psychology
laboratories." Until the period around 1880 to which Ebbinghaus was referring, psychology
was nowhere considered an independent scholarly discipline; rather it was a
facet of the "humane" or "moral' sciences which was the official
province of philosophy and the amateur pastime of any learned person.
Although three
additional quarter‑centuries have passed since Ebbinghaus' remark, the
history of psychology is still short enough to make it possible for the career
of one individual to span all, or almost all, of its brief history as a
science. Such an individual was Alexander Romanovich Luria (1902‑1977),
born into the
second generation of scientific psychologists but raised in circumstances that
immersed him in the basic issues which had motivated the founders of the
discipline.
Scientific
psychology was born almost simultaneously in America, England, Germany, and
Russia. Although textbooks credit Wilhelm Wundt with founding the first
experimental laboratory in Leipzig in 1879, the new approach to the study
of the mind was not really the province of any one person or country.
. . . Introduction
At almost the same time
William james was encouraging his students to conduct experiments at Harvard;
Francis Galton in England was initiating the first applications of intelligence
tests; and V1adimir Bekhtercv opened a laboratory in Kazan that explored most
of the problems which would later come to dominate the new science. Learning
mechanisms, alcoholism, and psychopathology were all under investigation in
Bekhterev's laboratory while Luria was growing up in Kazan.
Although
historical hindsight makes it possible to divide eras in psychology according
to the ideas that dominated its practitioners, the changes in the early years
of the twentieth century that were to render the "new psychology" of
the 1880s and 1890s an obsolete psychology by 1920 were by no means clear. Dissatisfaction with the
dominant psychologies had not yet resulted in a coherent opposition with a
positive program of its own. If matters were unclear in western Europe and
America, they were even murkier in Russia, where science labored under the
burden of heavy government censorship, guided by conservative religious
principles and autocratic political policies. Not until 1911 was the first officially recognized Institute of
Psychology founded at Moscow University. But even this progressive step was
blunted by the choice of a director whose research was based squarely on German
psychological theory of the 1880s.
Under such
conditions, a young Russian who became interested in psychology found himself
in a curious intellectual time warp. If he restricted himself to reading
Russian, his ideas about the subject matter and methods of psychology would be
old‑fashioned. Translations of important western European work became
available slowly and only in a quantity and range of subject that suited the
tsar's censor. Because of the sketchy evidence available in Russian, psychology
in Kazan in 1910 was at the same point as
psychology in Leipzig or Wurzburg a generation earlier.
But if a young
Russian read German, more recent work was available, especially if his family
moved in intellectual circles whose members went off to Germany to study. Such
was the
2
The Historical Context . . .
case with the Luria family. So
at a very young age, young Luria began to read more widely in contemporary
experimental psychology than work in translation would permit. Perhaps because
his father was a physician interested in psychosomatic medicine, the new work
in psychiatry spearheaded by jung and Freud also fell into Luria's hands. To
this he added the humanistic, philosophical ideas of the German romantic
tradition, especially those works which criticized the limitations of
laboratory psychology of the sort propounded by Wundt and his followers.
Thus, although
Luria was by virtue of his birth, a member of psychology's second generation,
he began his career immersed in the basic issues of those who had founded
psychology a quarter‑century earlier. Throughout his sixty years of
active research and theorizing, Luria never ceased to be concerned with these
fundamental problems. He constantly sought their resolution in the light of new
knowledge accumulated as succeeding generations of psychologists worked their
transformations on the fundamental material inherited from their progenitors.
The general
amnesia that afflicts the ahistorical discipline of psychology makes it
difficult to recover the dilemmas which Luria confronted as a young man.
Perhaps there is comfort to be derived from the notion that psychological ideas
at the turn of the century are as obsolete today as the automobiles which were
then being manufactured. But the course of material technology has proved a
poor analogy for progress in scientific psychology. A better analogy, which has
an honorable history in Russian thought of the late nineteenth century and in
Marxist writings of both the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, was provided
by Lenin, who remarked of progress in science that it is "a development
that repeats, as it were, the stages already passed, but repeats them in a
different way, on a higher plane . . . a development, so to speak, in spirals,
not in a straight line" (Lenin, 1934, p. 14).
The state of
psychology's spiral as Luria surveyed the intellectual landscape at the start
of his career was contentious. The major disagreement dividing scholars found
expression in sev
3 . . .
. . . Introduction
eral seemingly independent
arguments. Primary among these was whether psychology could be an objective,
experimental science.
The
"new" element in the "new psychology‑ of the 1880s was
experimentation. There was little innovation in the psychological categories
and theories offered by Wundt, whose main concepts could be traced back through
empirical philosophers like Locke all the way to Aristotle. For Wundt, as for the
psychologically inclined philosophers before him, the basic mechanism of mind
was the association of ideas, which arise from the environment in the form of
elementary sensations. Wundt's innovation was his claim that he could verify
such theories on the basis of controlled observations carried out in carefully
designed laboratory experiments. Introspection remained an essential part of
his method, but now it was "scientific" introspection that could
yield the general laws of the mind, not armchair speculation.
Wundt's
specific, theoretical claims did not go unchallenged. He was opposed from
within the new psychology by a variety of scholars whose data led them to
construct alternative theories of mental events. The disagreements that ensued
often centered on the validity of introspective reports, and a great deal of
controversy was generated about basic matters of fact. Eventually, the failure
to resolve these arguments, as well as the suspicion that they might be
irresolvable in principle because the events to which they referred were
internal reports of individuals rather than events observable by any unbiased
observer, brought an end to the first era of scientific psychology.
In many standard
discussions of this period (e.g. Boring, 1925, 1950) it goes unnoticed that the
arguments between Wundt and his critics within psychology were part of a larger
discussion about the appropriateness of experimentation altogether. While Wundt
and his successors were gathering facts and prestige for their burgeoning new
science, skeptics mourned the loss of the phenomena that had originally made
the human mind an important topic of study. This criticism was captured
4
The Historical Context . .
.
nicely by Henri Bergson in
quoting Shakespeare's phrase, "We murder to disse ct." Or as G. S.
Brett later put the choices "One way will lead to a psychology which is
scientific but artificial; the other will lead to a psychology which is natural
but cannot be scientific, remaining in the end an art" (Brett, 1930, p.
54).
The objection to
experimentation from critics was that restricting psychology to the laboratory
automatically restricted the mental phenomena it could investigate. There is
more to mental life than elementary sensations and their associations; there is
more to thinking than can be discerned in reaction time experiments. But it
seemed that only these elementary phenomena could be investigated in the
laboratory.
Wundt was not
indifferent to these criticisms. He acknowledged that the experimental method
has limitations, but he chose to confront them by making a distinction between
elementary and higher psychological functions. Whereas experimental psychology
was the appropriate way to study elementary psychological phenomena, the higher
functions could not be studied experimentally. In fact, the actual processes of
higher psychological functioning could probably not be ascertained at all. The
best that could be done was to study the products of the higher functions by
cataloguing cultural artifacts and folklore. In effect, Wundt ceded the study
of higher psychological functions to the discipline of anthropology as he knew
it. He devoted many years to this enterprise, which he termed volkerpsychologie.
The basic choice
between experimental and nonexperimental methods was of central concern to
Luria as he began his career, but he did not like any of the ready‑made
choices with which he was confronted. On all sides he saw compromise
formulations, none of which satisfied him. Like Wundt, Bekliterev, and others,
he believed firmly in the necessity for experimentation. But he also
sympathized with Wundt's critics, especially Wilhelm Dilthey, who had searched
ways to reconcile the simplifications entailed by Wundt's experimental approach
with humanistic analyses of complex human emotions and actions. Dilthey even
. . . Introduction
tually despaired, rejecting
experimentation as an altogether inappropriate way to study human psychological
processes. Luria, never given to despair, chose a different route. He sought a
new, synthetic method that would reconcile art and science, description and
explanation. He would remove artificiality from the laboratory, while retaining
the laboratory's analytic rigor. Having made this choice, he then faced a new
series of choices concerning method and theory that would make possible his
attempt at scientific synthesis.
Like countless
psychologists before him, Luria believed that a full understanding of the mind
had to include accounts of both the knowledge that people have about the world
and the motives that energize them as they put such knowledge to use. It was
important to know the origin of the basic processes through which knowledge is
acquired and the rules that describe psychological change. Change, for Luria
referred to the new kinds of systems into which the basic processes can be
organized. His very large task, still unrealized by any psychological theory
today, was to try to provide both a general framework and a set of specific
mechanisms to describe and explain all the systems of behavior that emerge from
the workings of the many subsystems that comprise the living individual.
Using this
global characterization of the human mind as a starting point, Luria had to
survey the existing experimental methods that could render his own approach
more than empty phrase‑mongering. Within the arena of knowledge, all
major techniques were elaborations of the notion that the structure of ideas
can be found in the structure of the associations into which they enter. German
laboratories had begun to use mechanical timing devices which they hoped would
yield a precise chronometry of mental associations. This technology had
advanced to the point where many investigators believed that it would be
possible to record the time required for different kinds of mental events.
Arguments focused on defining the units of mental activity and on determining
whether it was the association of elements or of mental acts that was being
"measured."
6
The Historical Context . .
.
During this same
period associative responses were being used for a quite different purpose by
medically oriented scholars such as Jung and Freud. While recognizing that
associations among words provided information about relations among ideas, they
were less interested in mapping their patients' conscious knowledge systems or
in timing associative responses than in using associations to discover
knowledge that the person was not aware of. Even more important was the
possibility that word associations could yield information about the motives,
hidden from consciousness, that were energizing otherwise unexplainable
behavior.
Luria saw in
these two disparate approaches to the method of word associations‑one
experimental, the other clinical‑the possibility of enriching the study
of knowledge and motivation, both of which he believed to be intricately
combined in any psychological process. His efforts to create a unified
psychology of mind from these beginnings represented the central theme of his life's
work. His willingness to work with motivational concepts put forth within the
psychoanalytic school might have placed him outside of academic psychology
altogether, but this did not happen for a number of reasons. First, Luria was
committed to the experimental method. just as important was his commitmerit to
the use of objective data as the basis for theorizing. When many psychologists
began to insist not just that observable behavior had to represent the basic
data for psychologists but also that psychological theories could not appeal to
unobservable events, Luria demurred, anticipating a position similar to that
defended by Edward Tolman years later. He treated consciousness and the
unconscious as intervening variables, that is, as concepts that organized the
patterns of behavioral data obtained.
Another issue
confronting psychologists at the turn of the century was their attitude toward
the "more basic" knowledge then accruing in physiology, neurology,
and anatomy, an area now termed the "neurosciences." The major
achievements of nineteenth‑century biology and physiology had made it
virtually
7 . . .
. . . Introduction
impossible to ignore important
links between the central nervous system and the "mentaP' phenomena that
were the psychologist's focus. But the question was whether psychology need
restrict itself to the phenomena that had been discovered in the physiological
laboratory. Here opinion was divided along two important lines.
As a matter of
principle, many psychologists rejected the notion that mind could be reduced to
"matter in motion" and that such matter could be studied in the
physiologists' laboratory. Mind, according to their view, had rather to be
studied introspectively, using itself as a basic investigative tool. At the
opposite extreme were scientists who claimed that psychology was no more than a
branch of physiology, which would provide a unified theory of behavior. This
position was taken by the Russian physiologist 1. M. Sechenov, whose Reflexes
of the Brain contained
an explicit program for explaining mental phenomena as the central link in the
reflex arc.
Between these
extreme positions, were many psychologists, including Luria, who believed that
psychology should develop in. a manner that was consistent with, but not entirely
dependent on, the neurosciences. They accepted the notion that psychological
phenomena were part of the natural world, subject to the laws of nature. But
they did not necessarily agree that any existing model of how the brain was
linked to psychological processes, especially complex processes, was correct.
So psychology had to proceed on its own, keeping an eye on physiology as it
progressed. Luria was among a very few psychologists who sought to extend the
areas of consistency, deliberately confronting both psychology and the
neurosciences with each other's facts and theories. Forty years after he had
begun such activities, a new, hybrid branch of psychology, called
"neuropsychology," won recognition as a scientific enterprise.
Another basic
distinction within psychology formed around the basic "building
blocks" of mind that the psychologist assumed. One group, associated
variously with the names of Wundt, E. B. Titchener, John Watson, and Clark
Hull, at
8
The Historical Context . .
.
tempted to identify the basic
elements of behavior as sensations that combined according to the laws of
association to form elementary ideas, or habits. Another group, among whom can
be counted Franz Brentano, William James, and the Gestalt psychologists,
resisted this "elementarism." Their analyses suggested that basic
psychological processes always reflected organizational properties that could
not be discovered in isolated elements. This idea was expressed variously in
terms like the "stream of consciousness," "unconscious
inference," and t'properties of the whole." The essence of this
position was that the reduction of mind into elements obliterated properties of
the intact, functioning organism that could not be retrieved once the reduction
had taken place.
In this
controversy Luria clearly sided against the elementarists, but his insistence
that basic units of analysis must retain their emergent properties did not
reduce to the arguments and phenomena then being explored by the Gestalt
psychologists. Luria very early insisted that the basic units of psychological
analysis were functions, each of which represented systems of elementary acts
that controlled organism‑environment relations.
Because of the
cross‑cutting choices and competing claims to scientific legitimacy in
psychology which constituted Luria's early intellectual milieu, it is not
possible to assign him to any one school. On each of the systematic issues
confronting psychology he made clear‑cut choices from the same set of
possibilities as his contemporaries, but his combination of choices was unique,
making him both a part of and separate from the major schools of psychology of
the early 1920s.
The new mixture
that Luria developed in collaboration with Lev Vygotsky, retained its
distinctiveness up to 1960. Luria's interest in the way that motives organize
behavior, coupled with his willingness to talk about "hidden
complexes," his use of free association techniques (albeit in conjunction
with tried‑and‑true reaction time methods), and his promotion of
psychoanalytic ideas make it tempting to view him as an early, experimental
Freudian. But even in his early writings on the subject, this des
9 . . .
. . . Introduction
ignation would not have fit.
Luria was not interested primarily in revealing the nature of the unconscious,
and he attributed far too great a role to man's social environment as a prime
shaper of individual behavior to be comfortable with Freud's biologizing of the
mind.
From the outset,
Luria carefully defended a methodology which relied upon objective data,
whether in the form of spoken responses, movements, or physiological
indicators, as the only acceptable data in psychology. This position might have
placed him among the behaviorists, had it not been for his willingness to talk
about unobservable states of mind and his insistence on the possibility of
using objective indicators to yield information about them. Luria would also
have been difficult to classify as a behaviorist because of the strong link
between early behaviorism and stimulus‑response, or reflex, theories. For
Luria, word associations were a useful tool with which to ferret out the
workings of a complicated psychological system, but he never accepted the idea
that associations among ideas, or between stimuli and responses, represented a
theory of how the mind works.
He unfavorably
identified stimulus‑response theories with the 94 telephone station‑
theory of how the central nervous system organized behavior, which likened the
central nervous system to a giant switchboard. He remarked wryly that "it
would be an interesting), work to follow the complete history of the
twentiethcentury natural science of analogy . . . of those models which are
accepted as a basis for the construction of ideas concerning forms and mechanisms
of human vital activity. This history should reveal many naive sources of human
thought . . . This tendency to introduce naive concepts to explain the nervous
system on the basis of analogies with artificial things is more cornmon in the
study of behavior than anywhere else" (Luria, 1932, p. 4). In place of a telephone
station, Luria suggested the idea of a dynamically organized system, composed
of subsystems, each of which contributed to the organization of the whole. In
the 1920s this
might have sounded like a version of Gestalt psychol
. . . 10
The Historical Context . .
.
ogy, but it could come as no
surprise to cognitive psychologists when more than thirty years later Luria
seized upon Miller, Galanter, and Pribrain's Plans and the Structure of
Behavior, a
pioneering effort to apply computer systems analysis to psychology, as a
kindred expression of concern for the limitations of stimulus response theory
and as a mechanical analogy which, despite its limitations, began to approach
his idea of what human systems might be like.
It might also
have been possible to consider Luria a physiological psychologist because of
his lifelong interest in the brain bases of behavior, except that for him the
study of the isolated brain could not reveal how behavior was organized.
Rather, he kept firmly in mind the fact that properties of the entire system
could not be reliably obtained from a study of its parts operating in
isolation. The brain was part of both a larger biological system and a
surrounding environmental system in which social organization was a powerful
force. Consequently, a psychological theory of the intact organism that
preserved its history of interactions with the environment and its task at the
time of study was a necessary complement to purely physiological or
neuroanatomic investigation.
All of these
ideas, which are to be found in Luria's writings as early as the 1920s, render him a prematurely
modern psychologist who happened to begin life before his ideas could find
confirmation in existing technologies or data. But it is not possible or
appropriate to locate Luria's ideas only in terms of world psychology and
neurophysiology. The fact that he was a Russian intellectual actively involved
in the building of Soviet science and psychology shaped his career from its
earliest days.
For
approximately a decade following the Revolution there was a great deal of
experimentation and improvization in the conduct of Soviet science, education,
and economic policy. Less well known than the political struggles after Lenin's
death are the experiments with new forms of schooling, free market agriculture,
modern means of expression in the arts, and new branches of science. During the
1920s, virtually
every psycho
. . . Introduction
logical movement existing in
western Europe and the United States found adherents in the Soviet Union.
Perhaps because psychology as an academic discipline was embryonic at the end
of the tsarist era, with only a single institute devoted to what was then
recognized as psychology proper, an unusual variety of viewpoints and
activities competed actively for the right to determine what the new Soviet
psychology should be like. Educators, doctors, psychiatrists, psychoanalysts,
neurologists. and physiologists often contributed to national meetings devoted
to discussions of research and theory.
As the decade
progressed, three issues came to dominate these discussions. First, there was
increasing concern that Soviet psychology should be self‑consciously
Marxist. No one was certain what this meant, but everyone joined in the
discussion with their own proposals. Second. psychology must be a materialist
discipline; all psychologists were obliged to search for the material basis of
mind. And third, psychology should have relevance to the building of a
socialist society. Lenin's exhortation that theory be tested in practice was a
matter of both economic and social urgency.
Toward the end
of the 1920s this discussion had progressed to a point where there was
agreement on some general principles, but the major conclusions did not single
out any existing approach as a model for others. At the same time, the country
experienced new economic and social upheavals with the advent of the rapid
collectivization of agriculture and a greatly accelerated pace of heavy
industrial development. Existing psychological schools were found to be wanting
in their practical contributions to these new social demands as well.
A major result
of these ideological and performance deficiencies was a deliberate
reorganization of psychological research in the mid‑1930s. While the
specific events associated with this reorganization grew out of dissatisfaction
with the use of psychological tests in education and industry, the result was a
general decline in the authority and prestige of psychology as a whole.
During World War 11 many psychologists, like Luria,
devoted
. . . 12
The Historical Context . .
.
their efforts to
rehabilitation of the wounded. Educational and medical psychology mixed freely
in the face of the devastation wrought by modern warfare. Following the war,
these two aspects of psychology continued to dominate Soviet psychology as the
country rebuilt itself. Psychology as a separate discipline remained dormant,
while psychological research was treated simply as a special feature of some
other scientific enterprise.
Then in the late
1940s, interest in the field of psychology revived, with a focus on the work of
Ivan Pavlov, Russia's renowned physiologist. Although many Americans think of
Pavlov as a psychologist, perhaps because his methods for studying conditioned reflexes
were adopted as both a key method and a theoretical model in American
psychology between 1920 and 1960, Pavlov resisted association with psychology
for most of his life. Soviet psychologists returned the compliment. They were
willing to grant Pavlov pre‑eminence in the field of the material basis
of mind; but they reserved the province of psychological phenomena,
particularly such "higher psychological processes" as deliberate
remembering, voluntary attention, and logical problem solving, to themselves.
As in this
country, many Soviet physiologists concerned with relations between the brain
and behavior did not like this division of scientific labor. In fact, they
considered psychology altogether unscientific. Given the opportunity, such
people, many of whom were students of Pavlov, were delighted with the chance to
make the study of "higher nervous activity" a model for psychology to
follow. As the result of an extraordinary set of meetings under the auspices of
the Academy of Medical sciences in 1950, psychologists began devoting major
energy and attention to the application of Pavlovian concepts and techniques in
their work. Special prominence was given to Pavlov's ideas concerning language,
which appeared a likely area for psychologists to exploit.
In the past
quarter‑century, Soviet psychology has grown enormously in size and
prestige. Important scientific advances in western European science,
particularly in the study of brain
13 . . .
. . . Introduction
functioning and computer
technology, have been adopted and become a part of indigenous Soviet science.
Psychology has not only gained recognition as an independent discipline but
also been included among the disciplines that make up the prestigious National
Academy of Sciences.
Throughout the
first six decades of Soviet psychology Alexander Luria labored to make it a
science that would fit the dreams of its originators, a Marxist study of man
which would be of service to people in a democratic, socialist society. In
pursuing this goal, Luria brought to bear firsthand experience with all of the
problems and insights accumulated throughout the world in psychology since its
inception one hundred years ago. His work is a monument to the intellectual and
humanistic traditions that represent the best of the human culture he labored
to understand and improve.
The Making of Mind